Navigation

Tarot

Astrology

Spiritual Reflections

Pagan Witchcraft

Artwork

Who Is Starweaver?

Archive of Past Issues

Site Index

Blog: Starweaver's Corner

Home

Quantum Weirdness II:
Schroedinger's Cat

The Role of the Observer

Measurement operations on a quantum system always give some definite answer, informing us that the system is in one of the definite states detectable by the measuring device. For example, an exposed grain of photographic film testifies that the electron was there and nowhere else when it deposited its energy in the detector. All subsequent observations will be consistent with the first. So, for example, if an electron is actually observed traversing slit 1, any future observations made on it will show it behaving as a small pellet that has gone through that slit, not as part of a superposition of slit-1 and slit-2 waves. The measurement observation changes the state of the system, replacing a superposition with a definite state.

What is it about the act of observation that causes such a change? Quantum systems are microscopic, simple, and have only small amounts of energy. Energy must be transferred to the measuring device if the quantum is to be detected at all, and that energy will be a significant amount of the total available, so it is obvious that measurement will be disruptive. But how is it that superpositions never survive an act of measurement? And what kind of interaction does it take to remove a superposition and put a quantum system in a definite state? Many attempts to probe these questions have centered around Erwin Schroedinger's famous thought experiment involving a cat in a box.

The Cat

From the amount of ink that has been spilled on this subject, one might assume that Schroedinger had devoted a whole book or at least a lengthy paper to the thought experiment when he introduced it. In fact, his mention of it is hardly more than an aside. In a general paper on quantum mechanics, he discusses and rejects the interpretation that a single quantum is somehow phyiscally "spread out" or "blurred" among the different parts of a superposition (for example, that the electron in the double slit experiment somehow makes itself into a cloud and manages to go through both slits). He then emphasizes this as follows:

One can even set up quite ridiculous cases. A cat is penned up in a steel chamber, along with the following diabolical device (which must be secured against direct interference by the cat): in a Geiger counter there is a tiny bit of radioactive substance, so small that perhaps in the course of one hour one of the atoms decays, but also, with equal probability, perhaps none; if it happens, the counter tube discharges and through a relay releases a hammer which shatters a small flask of hydrochloric acid. If one has left this entire system to itself for an hour, one would say that the cat still lives if meanwhile no atom has decayed. The first atomic decay would have poisoned it. The [wave] function of the entire system would express this by having in it the living and dead cat (pardon the expression) mixed or smeared out in equal parts.

It is typical of these cases that an indeterminacy originally restricted to the atomic domain becomes transformed into macroscopic indeterminacy, which can then be resolved by direct observation. That prevents us from so naively accepting as valid a "blurred model" for representing reality. In itself it would not embody anything unclear or contradictory. There is a difference between a shaky or out-of-focus photograph and a snapshot of clouds and fog banks.

Schroedinger's thought experiment has suffered much abuse at the hands of poorly informed writers. In many treatments, for example, it is taken for granted that a real cat placed in a box like the one described would be in a quantum superposition state until someone opens the box and looks at it. This is not true, and it confuses the lesson to be learned from the thought experiment. Unfortunately, Schroedinger was writing in the earliest days of quantum mechanics, before much attention had been given to the distinction between superposition and mixture states. Let's look first at what actually happens to Schroedinger's cat, and then return to the questions raised by the thought experiment.

Coherence

The distinguishing feature of a superposition state is the possibility of interference between its two components. If there were no inteference between the electrons passing through the two slits in the double-slit experiment, they would act just like classical particles and there would be no quantum weirdness. Interference, though, depends on some rather delicate conditions. The two waves must be in some way "keeping time" with one another in order for their crests and troughs to combine in the periodic, predictable manner needed to produce an interference pattern. If one of the waves is being constantly disrupted, so that there is no reliable periodicity in its wave forms, we would observe only a jumble of wave energy, not a geometrically regular interference pattern. Imagine, for example, that we decided to amplify one of the water waves from the double-slit experiment to make it easier to detect. We might do this by placing thousands of motorized paddles in the water around slit 2, with their "on" switches attached to very sensitive triggers so that any small disturbance in the water around the paddle will start the motor running and launch strong waves into the water in all directions. Now when the first water wave traverses the slit and brushes the first motorized paddle, it sets off a chain reaction. Before long, all the thousands of motors are running, and thousands of waves are being launched in all directions, none of them synchronized with the others, and all starting in different spots at different times. A huge amount of energy would be carried to the detector by this cascade of secondary waves, but there would no orderly pattern of wave crests at all, and the interference pattern between the slit-1 and slit-2 waves would be completely lost.

Such loss of coherence through amplification is an inescapable part of our knowledge of quantum phenomena. Individual quanta are too small to enter our awareness without what Bohr called "an irreversible act of amplification" taking place at some point or other...in a measurement apparatus or in our own sense organs. The decoherence that invariably accompanies such amplification destroys any original superposition state and leaves a mixture in its place.

In the cat scenario, the amplification takes place in the Geiger tube used to detect the radioactive decay. The radioactive atom may indeed be in a superposition of "decayed" and "undecayed" states, but when the emitted alpha particle causes the Geiger tube to discharge, the state of the system becomes a mixture. The state in which the tube discharged and the state in which it did not discharge cannot interfere with each other. From this point on, quantum weirdness is out of the picture: the relay, hammer, flask of acid, and cat all behave precisely as they do in classical physics. Although it is technically true that, until we open the box, we must describe the cat as a mixture of live and dead states, this means nothing more than simply saying that the cat may be dead or alive, and we do not yet know which.

Schroedinger, although he does not speak of superpositions and mixtures, clearly has this in mind when he says that any uncertainty in the state of a macroscopic system can be resolved by direct observation. He thinks it is wrong to imagine the cat as being something like a double-exposed photograph, dead and alive superimposed. The cat, as common sense tells us, is one way or the other; only our knowledge is incomplete.

So What's the Problem?

It might seem as if the process of decoherence can dispel these questions of the role of the observer in quantum mechanics. Decoherence through amplification is, after all, a purely physical process. No consciousness is required to make it happen. Our choice to look in the box has no effect on the subsequent behavior of the system; it only affects our state of knowledge about it.

In the Copenhagen Interpretation, all unobserved states (superpositions and mixtures both) are viewed very much alike from a philosophical standpoint. Because no observation has yet been made on them, they are not considered objectively real (since objectivity implies that different persons have a shared experience of the phenomenon, and before observation there is no experience to share!). Some of these unobserved states (the coherent ones) have interference terms in their descriptions, others do not. Either way, our description incorporates the incompleteness of our knowledge--knowledge that can only become complete through actual observation. With this philosophical orientation, one would indeed say that the cat is neither alive nor dead as a matter of objective reality until an observation is made.

From a philosophical orientation that is more metaphysical and less epistemological, there is no great difference between a pre-observation mixture and a post-observation single state. From this perspective, the objective reality of the cat's condition does not change on opening the box. If the cat is objectively dead, it became so the instant the flask broke, not at some later time when the box was opened. These two philosophical viewpoints are equally consistent with the facts; there is no experiment that can distinguish between them. It is more a matter of preference than of science.

The transition from superposition to mixture, and hence the transition for quantum weirdness to classical normalness, can indeed happen long before any human observes the system. In fact, it usually does. But this fact alone is not enough to completely separate the process of conscious observation from the behavior of quantum systems. Although we can have mixtures without observation, we still cannot have superpositions with observation. We can only directly observe states that are no longer in superposition. The coherence can be lost long before the observation, or it can be lost at the moment of observation, but it cannot be lost after the observation. Whenever we look we see something--something definite, the system in a well-defined state. In classical physics, we are free to assume that the system was in that state all along, before we bothered to look. In quantum mechanics, this assumption is sometimes possible (if we are observing a mixture), but soemtimes not (if we are observing a state that was in superposition).

Observation on a mixture state has no physical consequences, and so we are free to endulge either an epistemological or a metaphysical view of reality when it comes to mixtures; it makes no difference. But if you follow the metaphysical perspective, you enter a nightmare world when you try to extend your picture of reality to encompass the superposition states too. A dead cat and a live cat do not interfere with each other, but an electron going through slit 1 and an electron going through slit 2 do. Accounting for the interference and maintaing a picture of a single, localized, objectively real electron traversing the experimental apparatus is impossible. It is this impossibility that is demonstrated and put into experimentally testable terms by Bell's inequality.

In no case, however, should one think of consciousness as physically producing a change in the state of a system, either forcing a superposition into a mixture or forcing a mixture into a single state. Observing the cat does not kill the cat. It is very unfortunate that many popular writers on quantum mechanics have given this impression of the role of the observer. It is inconsistent with both the epistemological philosophy of the Copenhagen Interpretation and the metaphysical philosophy of hidden-variable approaches such as Bohm's.

 


Go to Quantum Weirdness III: Bell's Inequality

Return to Quantum Weirdness menu

Copyright © 2001-2008 Tom Waters